National Self-Sufficiency - by John Maynard Keynes (1933)
"...The decadent international but individualistic capitalism, in the hands of
which we found ourselves after the War, is not a success. It is not
intelligent, it is not beautiful, it is not just, it is not virtuous - and it
doesn't deliver the goods. In short, we dislike it and we are beginning to
despise it. But when we wonder what to put in its place, we are extremely
perplexed."...
I
I was brought up, like most Englishmen, to respect free trade not only as
an economic doctrine which a rational and instructed person could not doubt
but almost as a part of the moral law. I regarded departures from it as being
at the same time an imbecility and an outrage. I thought England's unshakable
free-trade convictions, maintained for nearly a hundred years, to be both the
explanation before man and the justification before heaven of her economic
supremacy. As lately as 1923 I was writing that free trade was based on
fundamental truths 'which, stated with their due qualifications, no one can
dispute who is capable of understanding the meaning of the words' [JMK, vol.
XIX, p. 147].
Looking again today at the statements of these fundamental truths which I
then gave, I do not find myself disputing them. Yet the orientation of my mind
is changed; and I share this change of mind with many others. Partly, indeed,
my background of economic theory is modified. I should not charge Mr Baldwin,
as I did then, with being 'a victim of the protectionist fallacy in its
crudest form', because he believed that, in the existing conditions, a tariff
might do something to diminish British unemployment. But mainly I attribute my
change of outlook to something else - to my hopes and fears and
preoccupations, along with those of many or most, I believe, of this
generation throughout the world, being different from what they were. It is a
long business to shuffle out of the mental habits of the pre-war
nineteenth-century world. But today, at last, one third of the way through the
twentieth century, we are most of us escaping from the nineteenth; and by the
time we reach its mid-point it is likely that our habits of mind and what we
care about will be as different from nineteenth-century methods and values as
each other century's has been from its predecessor's. It may be useful,
therefore, to attempt some sort of a stocktaking, of an analysis, of a
diagnosis, to discover in what this change of mind essentially consists.
What did the nineteenth-century free traders, who were amongst the most
idealistic and disinterested of men, believe that they were accomplishing?
They believed - and perhaps it is fair to put this first - that they were
being perfectly sensible, that they alone were clear sighted, and that the
policies which sought to interfere with the ideal international division of
labour were always the offspring of ignorance out of self-interest.
In the second place, they believed that they were solving the problem of
poverty, and solving it for the world as a whole, by putting to their best
uses, like a good housekeeper, the world's resources and abilities.
They believed, further, that they were serving not merely the survival of
the economically fittest but the great cause of liberty, of freedom for
personal initiative and individual gift, the cause of inventive art and the
fertility of the untrammelled mind against the forces of privilege and
monopoly and obsolescence. They believed, finally, that they were the friends
and assurers of peace and international concord and economic justice between
nations, and the diffusers of the benefits of progress.
And if to the poet of that age there sometimes came strange feelings to
wander far away where never comes the trader and catch the wild goat by the
hair, there came also with full assurance the comfortable reaction :
I, to herd with narrow foreheads, vacant of our glorious
gains,
Like a beast with lower pleasures, like a beast with lower pains!
(Locksley Hall, by Alfred Tennyson)
II
What fault have we to find with this? Taking it at its surface value -
none. Yet we are not, many of us, content with it as a working political
theory. What is wrong?
To begin with the question of peace. We are pacifist today with so much
strength of conviction that, if the economic internationalist could win this
point, he would soon recapture our support. But it does not now seem obvious
that a great concentration of national effort on the capture of foreign trade,
that the penetration of a country's economic structure by the resources and
the influence of foreign capitalists, that a close dependence of our own
economic life on the fluctuating economic policies of foreign countries, are
safeguards and assurances of international peace. It is easier, in the light
of experience and foresight, to argue quite the contrary. The protection of a
country's existing foreign interests, the capture of new markets, the progress
of economic imperialism - these are a scarcely avoidable part of a scheme of
things which aims at the maximum of international specialisation and at the
maximum geographical diffusion of capital wherever its seat of ownership.
Advisable domestic policies might often be easier to compass, if, for example,
the phenomenon known as' the flight of capital' could be ruled out. The
divorce between ownership and the real responsibility of management is serious
within a country when, as a result of joint-stock enterprise, ownership is
broken up between innumerable individuals who buy their interest today and
sell it tomorrow and lack altogether both knowledge and responsibility towards
what they momentarily own. But when the same principle is applied
internationally, it is, in times of stress, intolerable - I am irresponsible
towards what I own and those who operate what I own are irresponsible towards
me. There may be some financial calculation which shows it to be advantageous
that my savings should be invested in whatever quarter of the habitable globe
shows the greatest marginal efficiency of capital or the highest rate of
interest. But experience is accumulating that remoteness between ownership and
operation is an evil in the relations between men, likely or certain in the
long run to set up strains and enmities which will bring to nought the
financial calculation.
I sympathise, therefore, with those who would minimise, rather than with
those who would maximise, economic entanglement between nations. Ideas,
knowledge, art, hospitality, travel - these are the things which should of
their nature be international. But let goods be homespun whenever it is
reasonably and conveniently possible; and, above all, let finance be primarily
national. Yet, at the same time, those who seek to disembarrass a country of
its entanglements should be very slow and wary. It should not be a matter of
tearing up roots but of slowly training a plant to grow in a different
direction.
For these strong reasons, therefore, I am inclined to the belief that,
after the transition is accomplished, a greater measure of national
self-sufficiency and economic isolation between countries than existed in 1914
may tend to serve the cause of peace, rather than otherwise. At any rate the
age of economic internationalism was not particularly successful in avoiding
war; and if its friends retort that the imperfection of its success never gave
it a fair chance, it is reasonable to point out that a greater success is
scarcely probable in the coming years.
Let us turn from these questions of doubtful judgement, where each of us
will remain entitled to his own opinion, to a matter more purely economic. In
the nineteenth century the economic internationalist could probably claim with
justice that his policy was tending to the world's great enrichment, that it
was promoting economic progress, and that its reversal would have seriously
impoverished both ourselves and our neighbours. This raises a question of
balance between economic and non-economic advantage of a kind which is not
easily decided. Poverty is a great evil; and economic advantage is a real
good, not to be sacrificed to alternative real goods unless it is clearly of
an inferior weight. I am ready to believe that in the nineteenth century two
sets of conditions existed which caused the advantages of economic
internationalism to outweigh disadvantages of a different kind. At a time when
wholesale migrations were populating new continents, it was natural that the
men should carry with them into the New Worlds the material fruits of the
technique of the Old, embodying the savings of those who were sending them.
The investment of British savings in rails and rolling stock to be installed
by British engineers to carry British emigrants to new fields and pastures,
the fruits of which they would return in due proportion to those whose
frugality had made these things possible, was not economic internationalism
remotely resembling in its essence the part ownership of the A.E.G. of Germany
by a speculator in Chicago, or of the municipal improvements of Rio de Janeiro
by an English spinster. Yet it was the type of organisation necessary to
facilitate the former which has eventually ended up in the latter. In the
second place, at a time when there were enormous differences in degree in the
industrialisation and opportunities for technical training in different
countries, the advantages of a high degree of national specialisation were
very considerable.
But I am not persuaded that the economic advantages of the international
division of labour today are at all comparable with what they were. I must not
be understood to carry my argument beyond a certain point. A considerable
degree of international specialisation is necessary in a rational world in all
cases where it is dictated by wide differences of climate, natural resources,
native aptitudes, level of culture and density of population. But over an
increasingly wide range of industrial products, and perhaps of agricultural
products also, I become doubtful whether the economic cost of national
self-sufficiency is great enough to outweigh the other advantages of gradually
bringing the producer and the consumer within the ambit of the same national,
economic and financial organisation. Experience accumulates to prove that most
modern mass-production processes can be performed in most countries and
climates with almost equal efficiency. Moreover, as wealth increases, both
primary and manufactured products play a smaller relative part in the national
economy compared with houses, personal services and local amenities which are
not the subject of international exchange; with the result that a moderate
increase in the real cost of the former consequent on greater national
self-sufficiency may cease to be of serious consequence when weighed in the
balance against advantages of a different kind. National self-sufficiency, in
short, though it costs something, may be becoming a luxury which we can afford
if we happen to want it. Are there sufficient good reasons why we may happen
to want it?
III
The decadent international but individualistic capitalism, in the hands of
which we found ourselves after the War, is not a success. It is not
intelligent, it is not beautiful, it is not just, it is not virtuous - and it
doesn't deliver the goods. In short, we dislike it and we are beginning to
despise it. But when we wonder what to put in its place, we are extremely
perplexed.
Each year it becomes more obvious that the world is embarking on a variety
of politico-economic experiments, and that different types of experiment
appeal to different national temperaments and historical environments. The
nineteenth century free trader's economic internationalism assumed that the
whole world was, or would be, organised on a basis of private competitive
capitalism and of the freedom of private contract inviolably protected by the
sanctions of law - in various phases, of course, of complexity and
development, but conforming to a uniform type which it would be the general
object to perfect and certainly not to destroy. Nineteenth-century
protectionism was a blot upon the efficiency and good sense of this scheme of
things, but it did not modify the general presumption as to the fundamental
characteristics of economic society.
But today one country after another abandons these presumptions. Russia is
still alone in her particular experiment, but no longer alone in her
abandonment of the old presumptions. Italy, Ireland, Germany have cast their
eyes, or are casting them, towards new modes of political economy. Many more
countries after them will soon be seeking, one by one, after new economic
gods. Even countries such as Great Britain and the United States, though
conforming in the main to the old model, are striving, under the surface,
after a new economic plan. We do not know what will be the outcome. We are -
all of us, I expect - about to make many mistakes. No one can tell which of
the new systems will prove itself best.
But the point for my present discussion is this. We each have our own
fancy. Not believing that we are saved already, we each would like to have a
try at working out our own salvation. We do not wish, therefore, to be at the
mercy of world forces working out, or trying to work out, some uniform
equilibrium according to the ideal principles, if they can be called such, of
laissez-faire capitalism. There are still those who cling to the old ideas,
but in no country of the world today can they be reckoned as a serious force.
We wish - for the time at least and so long as the present transitional,
experimental phase endures - to be our own masters, and to be as free as we
can make ourselves from the interferences of the outside world.
Thus, regarded from this point of view, the policy of an increased national
self-sufficiency is to be considered not as an ideal in itself but as directed
to the creation of an environment in which other ideals can be safely and
conveniently pursued.
Let me give as dry an illustration of this as I can devise, chosen because
it is connected with ideas with which recently my own mind has been largely
preoccupied. In matters of economic detail, as distinct from the central
controls, I am in favour of retaining as much private judgement and initiative
and enterprise as possible. But I have become convinced that the retention of
the structure of private enterprise is incompatible with that degree of
material well-being to which our technical advancement entitles us, unless the
rate of interest falls to a much lower figure than is likely to come about by
natural forces operating on the old lines. Indeed the transformation of
society, which I preferably envisage, may require a reduction in the rate of
interest towards vanishing point within the next thirty years. But under a
system by which the rate of interest finds, under the operation of normal
financial forces, a uniform level throughout the world, after allowing for
risk and the like, this is most unlikely to occur. Thus for a complexity of
reasons, which I cannot elaborate in this place, economic internationalism
embracing the free movement of capital and of loanable funds as well as of
traded goods may condemn this country for a generation to come to a much lower
degree of material prosperity than could be attained under a different system.
But this is merely an illustration. The point is that there is no prospect
for the next generation of a uniformity of economic systems throughout the
world, such as existed, broadly speaking, during the nineteenth century; that
we all need to be as free as possible of interference from economic changes
elsewhere, in order to make our own favourite experiments towards the ideal
social republic of the future; and that a deliberate movement towards greater
national self-sufficiency and economic isolation will make our task easier, in
so far as it can be accomplished without excessive economic cost.
IV
There is one more explanation, I think, of the reorientation of our minds.
The nineteenth century carried to extravagant lengths the criterion of what
one can call for short the financial results, as a test of the advisability of
any course of action sponsored by private or by collective action. The whole
conduct of life was made into a sort of parody of an accountant's nightmare.
Instead of using their vastly increased material and technical resources to
build a wonder-city, they built slums; and they thought it right and advisable
to build slums because slums, on the test of private enterprise, 'paid',
whereas the wonder-city would, they thought, have been an act of foolish
extravagance, which would, in the imbecile idiom of the financial fashion,
have 'mortgaged the future' ; though how the construction today of great and
glorious works can impoverish the future no man can see until his mind is
beset by false analogies from an irrelevant accountancy. Even today we spend
our time - half vainly, but also, I must admit, half successfully - in trying
to persuade our countrymen that the nation as a whole will assuredly be richer
if unemployed men and machines are used to build much needed houses than if
they are supported in idleness. For the minds of this generation are still so
beclouded by bogus calculations that they distrust conclusions which should be
obvious, out of a reliance on a system of financial accounting which casts
doubt on whether such an operation will 'pay'. We have to remain poor because
it does not 'pay' to be rich. We have to live in hovels, not because we cannot
build palaces, but because we cannot 'afford' them.
The same rule of self-destructive financial calculation governs every walk
of life. We destroy the beauty of the countryside because the unappropriated
splendours of nature have no economic value. We are capable of shutting off
the sun and the stars because they do not pay a dividend. London is one of the
richest cities in the history of civilisation, but it cannot 'afford' the
highest standards of achievement of which its own living citizens are capable,
because they do not 'pay'.
If I had the power today I should surely set out to endow our capital
cities with all the appurtenances of art and civilisation on the highest
standards of which the citizens of each were individually capable, convinced
that what I could create, I could afford - and believing that money thus spent
would not only be better than any dole, but would make unnecessary any dole.
For with what we have spent on the dole in England since the War we could have
made our cities the greatest works of man in the world.
Or again, we have until recently conceived it amoral duty to ruin the
tillers of the soil and destroy the age-long human traditions attendant on
husbandry if we could get a loaf of bread thereby a tenth of a penny cheaper.
There was nothing which it was not our duty to sacrifice to this Moloch and
Mammon in one; for we faithfully believed that the worship of these monsters
would overcome the evil of poverty and lead the next generation safely and
comfortably, on the back of compound interest, into economic peace.
Today we suffer disillusion, not because we are poorer than we were - on
the contrary even today we enjoy, in Great Britain at least, a higher standard
of life than at any previous period - but because other values seem to have
been sacrificed and because, moreover, they seem to have been sacrificed
unnecessarily. For our economic system is not, in fact, enabling us to exploit
to the utmost the possibilities for economic wealth afforded by the progress
of our technique, but falls far short of this, leading us to feel that we
might as well have used up the margin in more satisfying ways.
But once we allow ourselves to be disobedient to the test of an
accountant's profit, we have begun to change our civilisation. And we need to
do so very warily, cautiously and self-consciously. For there is a wide field
of human activity where we shall be wise to retain the usual pecuniary tests.
It is the state, rather than the individual, which needs to change its
criterion. It is the conception of the Chancellor of the Exchequer as the
chairman of a sort of joint-stock company which has to be discarded. Now if
the functions and purposes of the state are to be thus enlarged, the decision
as to what, broadly speaking, shall be produced within the nation and what
shall be exchanged with abroad, must stand high amongst the objects of policy.
V
From these reflections on the proper purposes of the state I return to the
world of contemporary politics. Having sought to understand and to do full
justice to the ideas which underlie the urge felt by so many countries today
towards greater national self-sufficiency, we have to consider with care
whether in practice we are not too easily discarding much of value which the
nineteenth century achieved. In those countries where the advocates of
national self-sufficiency have attained power, it appears to my judgement
that, without exception, many foolish things are being done. Mussolini may be
acquiring wisdom teeth. But Russia exhibits the worst example which the world,
perhaps, has ever seen of administrative incompetence and of the sacrifice of
almost everything that makes life worth living to wooden heads. Germany is at
the mercy of unchained irresponsibles - though it is too soon to judge her
capacity of achievement. The Irish Free State, a unit much too small for a
high degree of national insufficiency except at crushing economic cost, is
discussing plans which might, if they were carried out, be ruinous.
Meanwhile, those countries which maintain, or are adopting, straightforward
protectionism of the old-fashioned type, refurbished with the addition of a
few of the new plan quotas, are doing many things incapable of rational
defence. Thus, if the Economic Conference were to achieve a mutual reduction
of tariffs and prepare the way for regional agreements, it would be matter for
sincere applause. For I must not be supposed to be endorsing all those things
which are being done in the political world today in the name of economic
nationalism. Far from it. But I seek to point out that the world towards which
we are uneasily moving is quite different from the ideal economic
internationalism of our fathers, and that contemporary policies must not be
judged on the maxims of that former faith.
I see three outstanding dangers in economic nationalism and in the
movements towards national self-sufficiency.
The first is Silliness - the silliness of the doctrinaire. It is nothing
strange to discover this in movements which have passed somewhat suddenly from
the phase of midnight high-flown talk into the field of action. We do not
distinguish, at first, between the colour of the rhetoric with which we have
won a people's assent and the dull substance of the truth of our message.
There is nothing insincere in the transition. Words ought to be a little wild,
for they are the assault of thoughts upon the unthinking. But when the seats
of power and authority have been attained there should be no more poetic
licence. On the contrary, we have to count the cost down to the penny which
our rhetoric has despised. An experimental society has need to be far more
efficient than an old-established one, if it is to survive safely. It will
need all its economic margin for its own proper purposes and can afford to
give nothing away to softheadedness or doctrinaire folly.
The second danger - and a worse danger than silliness - is Haste. Paul Valéry's
aphorism is worth quoting - 'Political conflicts distort and disturb the
people's sense of distinction between matters of importance and matters of
urgency.' The economic transition of a society is a thing to be accomplished
slowly. What I have been discussing is not a sudden revolution, but the
direction of secular trend. We have a fearful example in Russia today of the
evils of insane and unnecessary haste. The sacrifices and losses of transition
will be vastly greater if the pace is forced. This is above all true of a
transition towards greater national self-sufficiency and a planned domestic
economy. For it is of the nature of economic processes to be rooted in time. A
rapid transition will involve so much pure destruction of wealth that the new
state of affairs will be, at first, far worse than the old, and the grand
experiment will be discredited.
The third risk, and the worst risk of all three, is Intolerance and the
stifling of instructed criticism. The new movements have usually come into
power through a phase of violence or quasi-violence. They have not convinced
their opponents; they have downed them. It is the modern method - to depend on
propaganda and to seize the organs of opinion; it is thought to be clever and
useful to fossilise thought and to use all the forces of authority to paralyse
the play of mind on mind. For those who have found it necessary to employ all
methods whatever to attain power, it is a serious temptation to continue to
use for the task of construction the same dangerous tools which wrought the
preliminary house-breaking.
Russia, again, furnishes us with an example of the blunders which a regime
makes when it has exempted itself from criticism. The explanation of the
incompetence with which wars are always conducted on both sides may be found
in the comparative exemption from criticism which the military hierarchy
affords to the high command. I have no excessive admiration for politicians,
but, brought up as they are in the very breath of criticism, how much superior
they are to the soldiers! Revolutions only succeed because they are conducted
by politicians against soldiers. Paradox though it be - who ever heard of a
successful revolution conducted by soldiers against politicians? But we all
hate criticism. Nothing but rooted principle will cause us willingly to expose
ourselves to it.
Yet the new economic modes, towards which we are blundering, are, in the
essence of their nature, experiments. We have no clear idea laid up in our
minds beforehand of exactly what we want. We shall discover it as we move
along, and we shall have to mould our material in accordance with our
experience. Now for this process bold, free and remorseless criticism is a sine
qua non of ultimate success. We need the collaboration of all the bright
spirits of the age. Stalin has eliminated every independent, critical mind,
even when it is sympathetic in general outlook. He has produced an environment
in which the processes of mind are atrophied. The soft convolutions of the
brain are turned to wood. The multiplied bray of the loud speaker replaces the
inflections of the human voice. The bleat of propaganda, as Low has shown us,
bores even the birds and the beasts of the field into stupefaction. Let Stalin
be a terrifying example to all who seek to make experiments. If not, I, at any
rate, will soon be back again in my old nineteenth-century ideals, where the
play of mind on mind created for us the inheritance which we are seeking today
to divert to our own appropriate purposes.
(The Yale Review, VOLUME XXII (1932-1933), Summer 1933), p. 755-759). As
reproduced by Panarchy
Read also "John
Maynard Keynes: a vision for the future or a ghost from the past?.- by
Richard Ebeling - June 8, 2012